Putnam and the Civil Society

Ian Fasel (ianfasel@mail.utexas.edu)
Wed, 17 Feb 1999 06:13:07 -0600

Putnam and the Civil Society

Putnam and the Civil Society

In Making Democracy Work, Robert Putnam describes and theorizes upon his massive study taken between 1970 and 1991 of the development of democratic institutions in modern Italy. Though he spares the reader from much of the detail present in his research, Putnam nevertheless offers a compelling and factually complete record of how regional governments in Italy evolved, and presents a strong case that the primary reason for governmental success, after economics, is something he calls "social capital". Putnam has drawn the conclusion that good civil society is measured by a population's level of associations and membership in non-governmental organizations, that there is some sort of causal relationship between the two, and that lack of this social capital will result in decreased performance in government.
Many have criticized Putnam for unsuccessfully addressing the simple truth that above all other causes, economic factors are the prime actor in governmental success. "Does it not stand to reason that when a society has more wealth and prosperity people have more time to engage in recreational, non-governmental activities?" critics argue. In fact, Putnam does not disagree with this statement at all. "Nothing is more obvious even to the casual observer than the fact that effective democracy is closely associated with socioeconomic modernity, both across time and across space," he says. But Putnam warns against using common sense and overall impressions (which are often disproportionately influenced by individual events) as the primary basis for making evaluations. Putnam notes that despite the many blanket statements people make about causes for governmental effectiveness, these statements are very infrequently backed up by empirical data. When put to the test, Putnam finds that although the correlation between economic success is strong, which stands to common sense, it does not in fact explain everything, and in fact explains very little other than a general trend.
Putnam then goes on to demonstrate how powerful good methodology is in revealing real relationships that can be concretely measured and discussed as facts rather than opinions, and shows a scientific rigor that would make most social scientists blush (but which would likely seem commonplace to other natural scientists). Despite the strongest complaints of political philosophers, one must not forget that everything Putnam says is backed up by twenty years of meticulous work and hard data.
It is with this mountain of evidence that Putnam shows strong correlation between membership in NGOs and governmental success. While governmental effectiveness vs. economic strength align themselves into rough correlation, Putnam's data shows that there are several other factors which correlate much more strongly with governmental success (at least after the measured success is normalized with respect to economic wealth.) Thus, "Campania, the region around Naples, is much more advanced economically than Molise and Basilicata, at the very bottom of the developmental hierarchy, but the latter two governments are visibly more effective than Campania's." The correlation between performance and economics is only r = 0.72. Meanwhile, the correlation between civic community and performance is so strong, r = 0.92, that "when we take the 'civic-ness' of a region into account, the relationship we previously observed between economic development and institutional performance entirely vanishes."
Putnam's next step is to attempt to explain the reason for these correlations, and here is where he gets in trouble with critics. Many opponents to Putnam's theory argue that the ideas presented showing the importance of social capital to governmental performance (discussed in detail in other papers on this web site) are only relevant to Italy, and that this limited study cannot be universally applied outside that single country. But in fact, Putnam takes pains to show that while he believes these correlations can be universalized, he does not have adequate evidence to support it to the same extent, and even labels one primary section for discussion of the causal relationships "The Civic Community:
Some Theoretical Speculations" (my italics). While he feels justified in drawing these comparisons, citing studies of Latin America (Hirshcman, 1977), assorted Third World countries (Esman, Upman, etc.), and even Almond and Verba's comparative study of civic culture in five nations of varying economic development (1966), all of which support his comparison, he carefully qualifies his speculation as just that: speculation.
Nevertheless, in exploring possible explanations for the differences in success between different regional governments, Putnam winds up showing with reliable data a truth which many philosophers have been aware of for centuries: that civil society must develop organically, and cannot be artificially implanted. Classical philosophers, including Plato and Aristotle, had long been hinting at what Hegel eventually described as a dialectical progression of institutions. Institutions, he states, are in a continuous state of change and modification by the citizens who participate in them, leading in his belief ultimately to a constitutional monarchy, what Zakaria might have called a liberal (even if not a strictly democratic) government. Weber and Foucault both echo this understanding, though Foucault paints a somewhat darker picture of humans as being in a constant power struggle with institutions that reach deep into every aspect of life. These philosophers all predict (to varying degrees) the failure of institutions that do not naturally arise out of the political life of a nation, a phenomenon demonstrated by Southern Italy's lack of success in producing effective democracies, a truth further supported by similar studies in Latin America (cited by Putnam) which show the low success rate of imported "grass-roots" organizations that are not truly grass-roots.
Thus, while attempting to contradict Putnam's findings, Sheri Berman's analysis of the role of grass-roots organizations in Nazi Germany can be seen in many ways to support Putnam's theory. Weimar Germans had lived under a long tradition of Imperial rule, thanks to Otto von Bismark's careful construction of a strong central government with weak representational rule (and thus a weak Reichstag, easily taken over and collapsed by Hitler and his party), a government that was able to avoid the questions of nation and race that the French had been struggling with since the eighteenth century. Thus, the grass-roots organizations manipulated by Nazi politicians were on weak historical ground, had little precedent for participating in a positive dialectical progression, and were thus susceptible to the volatility that older, more deeply rooted institutions might have resisted. The fact that "for civil society to have the beneficial effects neo-Toquevilleans posit, the political context has to be right," as Berman states, in no way weakens Putnam's argument-- it simply qualifies it. Even as social capitol was great in Germany before the Nazi's took over, in the wrong political climate it was easily manipulated by the key Nazi tactic of deception and treachery, so that once Nazi's did seize control, civic trust rapidly disappeared, and German government ceased to be good. The lesson then is not that civic society is bad, but that civic society must exist in the proper political environment, particularly one in which it has naturally grown out of the continuing dialectical progression, and is thus safer from the tactics of untruth and deception of extremist, racist groups.
Even if there are discrepancies in Putnam's explanations that must be addressed, the correlations he finds between civic mindedness and governmental success still exist. Provided that certain qualifications are taken into account, ala Berman's warnings about Germany, the fact that the correlation between governmental effectiveness and social capitol is consistently much higher than the correlation between governmental effectiveness and economic success cannot be ignored. Even if individuals dispute the explanations Putnam suggests, it is irresponsible to deny these correlations just because they suggest difficulty for the reader's favorite non-Western nation to achieve a Western style democracy.
Putnam's study says that civil society requires a certain political environment where individuals are free to discuss and associate in the first place. It likewise shows that socioeconomic development is highly advantageous to nations attempting to build a strong Western style democracy, at least by the yardstick of responsiveness, continuity, and ability to provide social services outlined by Putnam. Those who argue with Putnam will be hard pressed to show where any other nations have had similar results without following the conditions for success Putnam outlines. There is no reason why someone might choose a different yardstick by which to measure the success of a government, but this leads the discussion into a territory where Putnam makes no comment. So long as government success is measured by the same standards Putnam uses to evaluate quality, opposing theories must always be able to answer the question "Sounds plausible, but can you prove it?" This is a question Putnam is very successful at answering, and which opponents must learn to answer as well if they hope to make a strong case countervailing these theories.